Home / Chroniques / Can neuroscience solve the mystery of consciousness?
blurred portrait of a man with schizophrenic and mental disorders on a dark background. Stress and paranoia
Généré par l'IA / Generated using AI
π Neuroscience

Can neuroscience solve the mystery of consciousness?

1673120250801
Laure Tabouy
Doctor of Neuroscience and PhD student in Neuroethics at Université d'Aix-Marseille
Key takeaways
  • Neuroscience remains a relatively new academic discipline, and there is no theoretical consensus on what consciousness really is.
  • Consciousness is a complex subject of study, and recent technological advances have raised hopes that its physical markers can be identified.
  • The global workspace theory is a popular theory in neuroscience, which describes what consciousness does in a perceptible way.
  • Certain theories pose ethical problems, such as confinement to a materialism that neglects other possible dimensions of consciousness.
  • In particular, we must not forget an essential ethical question: are current technological developments really serving humanity?

Iden­ti­fy­ing what con­scious­ness is has become the Holy Grail of neu­ro­science. But can con­scious­ness be reduced to what can be observed in a lab­o­ra­to­ry? And what ethics should be applied to this new dis­ci­pline, which rais­es the dual hopes of sig­nif­i­cant med­ical advances and sub­stan­tial finan­cial gains? We dis­cuss this with Lau­re Tabouy, a neu­ro­sci­en­tist and ethi­cist who is pur­su­ing a sec­ond PhD in the ethics of neu­ro­science, dig­i­tal tech­nol­o­gy, neu­rotech­nolo­gies and arti­fi­cial intel­li­gence at the Cen­tre Gilles Gas­ton Granger (CGGG UMR 7304) at Aix-Mar­seille Uni­ver­si­ty, dur­ing which she is con­duct­ing a crit­i­cal analy­sis of the neu­roethics imposed by the devel­op­ment of neu­rotech­nolo­gies and the con­ver­gence of neu­ro­science and AI.

What kind of field of study is consciousness?

Lau­re Tabouy. Con­scious­ness is one of the most com­plex areas of study, falling with­in the scope of both phi­los­o­phy and neu­ro­science, as it encom­pass­es var­i­ous inter­twined dimen­sions: aware­ness of the out­side world and of one­self, the abil­i­ty to reflect on and analyse one’s own thoughts and actions, the source of free will, and the capac­i­ty for moral judge­ment. Since Socrates, it has been one of the major sub­jects of study for philoso­phers and has become a focus for neu­ro­science since the 1960s. Since the 2000s, the con­ver­gence of nan­otech­nol­o­gy, biotech­nol­o­gy, com­put­er sci­ence and cog­ni­tive sci­ence has raised hopes that increas­ing­ly sophis­ti­cat­ed tech­nolo­gies will make it pos­si­ble to iden­ti­fy the phys­i­cal mark­ers of con­scious­ness, and even of reflec­tive con­scious­ness. In par­al­lel with these exper­i­ments on brain activ­i­ty, var­i­ous neu­ro­sci­en­tif­ic the­o­ries known as “the­o­ries of con­scious­ness” have flour­ished in recent decades.

In France, the “global workspace theory”, proposed in the late 1980s by the American Bernard Baars and developed by the French neuroscientists Stanislas Dehaene, Lionel Naccache and Jean-Pierre Changeux, seems to have won widespread acceptance among neuroscientists. Could you explain what this theory consists of?

It is a so-called func­tion­al the­o­ry, which is very inter­est­ing from a con­cep­tu­al point of view and is not incon­sis­tent with cer­tain obser­va­tions made in the lab­o­ra­to­ry. It does not describe what con­scious­ness is, but what it does in a per­cep­ti­ble way. Accord­ing to this the­o­ry, the brain func­tions like a the­atre: con­scious thoughts occu­py the front of the stage, also known as the “glob­al work­space”, while in the back­ground, spe­cialised auto­mat­ic process­es locat­ed in the brain are con­stant­ly at work, pro­cess­ing sen­so­ry stim­uli. At any giv­en moment, only the results of some of these process­es are brought into the spot­light, there­by becom­ing acces­si­ble to all the auto­mat­ic neur­al process­es oper­at­ing behind the scenes.

Pro­po­nents of this the­o­ry pos­tu­late that the glob­al work­space is made up of neu­rons with long axons, capa­ble of trans­mit­ting infor­ma­tion to very dis­tant areas of the brain. In their view, the emer­gence of con­scious­ness would there­fore man­i­fest itself through the acti­va­tion of these vast cere­bral networks.

Do other theories exist?

Around thir­ty of them! Of course, not all of them have the same res­o­nance with­in the sci­en­tif­ic com­mu­ni­ty – or in the media and among fund­ing bod­ies. One of the main com­peti­tors to the glob­al work­space the­o­ry is the “inte­grat­ed infor­ma­tion the­o­ry”, pro­posed by Ital­ian neu­ro­sci­en­tist and psy­chi­a­trist Giulio Tononi in 2004. Rather than start­ing from brain activ­i­ty to iso­late the mark­ers of con­scious­ness, it sets out a glob­al the­o­ret­i­cal frame­work of what con­scious­ness is, sup­port­ed by a math­e­mat­i­cal mod­el. This the­o­ry defines con­scious­ness as an emer­gent prop­er­ty of any phys­i­cal struc­ture capa­ble of inte­grat­ing infor­ma­tion, and it applies this def­i­n­i­tion not only to the brain, but also to any infor­ma­tion-pro­cess­ing sys­tem. The degree of con­scious­ness of a sys­tem would thus depend on the amount of infor­ma­tion it is capa­ble of pro­cess­ing and its abil­i­ty to com­pare this infor­ma­tion at dif­fer­ent lev­els, both region­al and global.

Again, this is not incon­sis­tent with what can be observed local­ly in the brain. But it leads pro­po­nents of this the­o­ry to con­sid­er arti­fi­cial sys­tems such as ther­mostats or pho­to­di­odes as “con­scious” – an exten­sion of the con­cept of con­scious­ness about which many neu­ro­sci­en­tists have seri­ous objections.

This the­o­ry has been talked about as much for its nov­el­ty, even provoca­tive­ness, as for the fact that 124 researchers have labelled it pseu­do­science1 in a preprint (editor’s note: a ver­sion of a sci­en­tif­ic pub­li­ca­tion that pre­cedes its accep­tance by the edi­to­r­i­al board of a sci­en­tif­ic jour­nal) pub­lished on the PsyArX­iv plat­form. How­ev­er, this doc­u­ment remains rather light­weight from a sci­en­tif­ic point of view and is itself high­ly con­tro­ver­sial with­in the neu­ro­science community.

So, there is no theoretical consensus within the field of neuroscience on what consciousness is?

No. A recent col­lab­o­ra­tive study2 com­pared the glob­al work­space the­o­ry and the inte­grat­ed infor­ma­tion the­o­ry accord­ing to a pro­to­col estab­lished by a con­sor­tium that claims to be neu­tral in the­o­ret­i­cal terms. Their results con­firm cer­tain pre­dic­tions by both the­o­ries but also call into ques­tion some of their key prin­ci­ples. Ulti­mate­ly, this is not very sur­pris­ing. Neu­ro­science is still a rel­a­tive­ly new aca­d­e­m­ic dis­ci­pline. It has yet to find its inter­nal the­o­ret­i­cal con­ver­gence, and this con­ver­gence will like­ly come about through the com­bi­na­tion of sev­er­al theories.

You mentioned a plurality of dimensions intertwined in consciousness. Do these “theories of consciousness” encompass all these dimensions?

Pop­u­lar neu­ro­science often takes a reduc­tion­ist approach, mean­ing that it views its sub­ject (con­scious­ness) as the result of sub­sys­tems (brain process­es or the organ­i­sa­tion­al struc­ture of infor­ma­tion, for the two the­o­ries men­tioned). Reduc­tion­ism is not a prob­lem in itself: it allows us to define a frame­work that makes the exper­i­ment pos­si­ble. This is eas­i­ly under­stand­able, giv­en that it already places a prism between us and real­i­ty, through which cer­tain dimen­sions of con­scious­ness may escape.

But the most wide­ly pub­li­cised neu­ro­sci­en­tif­ic the­o­ries – includ­ing, above all, the glob­al work­space the­o­ry and, to a cer­tain extent, the inte­grat­ed infor­ma­tion the­o­ry – are also based on rad­i­cal mate­ri­al­ism: they assume that con­scious­ness can be reduced to phys­i­cal process­es. This is a major philo­soph­i­cal assump­tion, which can – and must – be ques­tioned. It is not itself the result of sci­en­tif­ic con­sen­sus, and phi­los­o­phy, from which it is derived, offers a wealth of alter­na­tive mod­els to explain what con­scious­ness is: ide­al­ism, cer­tain forms of plu­ral­ism, dual­ism (par­tic­u­lar­ly Carte­sian dual­ism), spir­i­tu­al­ism, etc. In fact, there is no rea­son­able basis for defin­i­tive­ly favour­ing a mate­ri­al­ist con­cep­tion of consciousness.

How do you explain this fundamental adoption of radical materialism?

It seems to me to stem from the very con­di­tions in which neu­ro­science itself was born. It was the emer­gence of extreme­ly pow­er­ful tech­nolo­gies for observ­ing brain activ­i­ty that moti­vat­ed its emer­gence. The incred­i­ble effec­tive­ness of these devices has, in a way, blind­ed us: we have con­fused what we are able to see now or will be able to see in the future – which is, indeed, incred­i­bly rich – with real­i­ty as a whole. The search for fund­ing also plays a role in this stance: it is more mar­ketable to say that we are going to get to grips with con­scious­ness than to announce that we hope to make progress in observ­ing some of the phys­i­cal phe­nom­e­na linked to the con­scious activ­i­ty of the brain…

Fundamentally, why does this materialist option pose an ethical problem?

It becomes prob­lem­at­ic when it is con­sid­ered the only way to access the truth of what con­scious­ness is. In this case, it is an ide­o­log­i­cal stance that pro­found­ly dis­torts eth­i­cal debates by cre­at­ing a biased cli­mate for reflec­tion. Based on this mate­ri­al­ist premise, some peo­ple are begin­ning to talk about the pos­si­bil­i­ty of down­load­ing con­scious­ness in the future, for exam­ple. This tran­shu­man­ist ide­ol­o­gy is techno­sci­en­tif­ic in nature and is already steer­ing research, polit­i­cal and finan­cial choic­es in a direc­tion that is high­ly ques­tion­able from an eth­i­cal stand­point. Neu­rotech­nol­o­gy com­pa­nies are clear­ly adopt­ing this bias by announc­ing that they can ‘read your brain’ or ‘deci­pher your brain waves to exploit your unsus­pect­ed abilities’.

The prospect of humans con­trol­ling their own con­scious­ness is so fas­ci­nat­ing that it obscures oth­er press­ing issues. How far are we will­ing to go in arti­fi­cial­ly mod­i­fy­ing the human brain? How can we assess the impact of neu­rotech­nol­o­gy on human evo­lu­tion, and is this where we col­lec­tive­ly want to go? And the ques­tion that dri­ves my the­sis: how can we free neu­roethics from the polit­i­cal and eco­nom­ic tech­noso­lu­tion­ist stran­gle­hold imposed by the devel­op­ment of neu­rotech­nolo­gies and the con­ver­gence of neu­ro­science and AI? It is cru­cial that ethics be a part of this dis­cus­sion, which is not real­ly the case at the moment.

A Recommendation3 from the Council on responsible innovation in the field of neurotechnologies was issued by the OECD in 2019, which was adopted in France in the form of a charter4 co-signed by numerous research organisations. UNESCO is also preparing a recommendation that should be published in November 2025. It seems that ethics in neuroscience is becoming more organised…

The ethics of neu­ro­science is a recent devel­op­ment: it can be said to have emerged as a branch of ethics in its own right only in 2002, at the San Fran­cis­co con­fer­ence on ‘neu­roethics’. The texts you refer to were writ­ten in the con­text of geopo­lit­i­cal tur­moil asso­ci­at­ed with the launch of huge brain research projects, such as the Human Brain Project5 under­tak­en on the ini­tia­tive of the Euro­pean Com­mis­sion and the Brain Ini­tia­tive6 launched by the Oba­ma admin­is­tra­tion. These texts are less the result of gen­uine eth­i­cal reflec­tion, ques­tion­ing the foun­da­tions and con­se­quences of ongo­ing tech­no­log­i­cal devel­op­ments, than an attempt to keep pace with these devel­op­ments, dri­ven essen­tial­ly by mar­ket forces.

What would it take for a genuine ethical reflection to emerge?

Dis­sent­ing voic­es exist among philoso­phers, ethi­cists and neu­ro­sci­en­tists them­selves, but they are cur­rent­ly being sti­fled… A gen­uine eth­i­cal reflec­tion must be based on a real philo­soph­i­cal, anthro­po­log­i­cal and cul­tur­al con­tro­ver­sy. It must be borne in mind that West­ern mate­ri­al­ist the­o­ries are far from uni­ver­sal. Beyond the philo­soph­i­cal cur­rents already men­tioned, almost all spir­i­tu­al­i­ties and reli­gions have a non-mate­ri­al­ist view of con­scious­ness. This should prompt us to shift our the­o­ret­i­cal focus. Ethics must also remain inde­pen­dent of the finan­cial inter­ests linked to the tech­no­log­i­cal devel­op­ments it ques­tions. And final­ly, it must keep its focus on the one ques­tion that ulti­mate­ly mat­ters: are these tech­no­log­i­cal devel­op­ments tru­ly serv­ing human­i­ty in all its dimensions?

Interview by Anne Orliac
1https://​osf​.io/​p​r​e​p​r​i​n​t​s​/​p​s​y​a​r​x​i​v​/​z​s​r​78_v1
2Cog­i­tate Con­sor­tium., Fer­rante, O., Gors­ka-Klimows­ka, U. et al. Adver­sar­i­al test­ing of glob­al neu­ronal work­space and inte­grat­ed infor­ma­tion the­o­ries of con­scious­ness. Nature 642, 133–142 (2025). https://doi.org/10.1038/s41586-025–08888‑1
3https://​legalin​stru​ments​.oecd​.org/​f​r​/​i​n​s​t​r​u​m​e​n​t​s​/​O​E​C​D​-​L​E​G​A​L​-0457
4https://​www​.enseigne​mentsup​-recherche​.gouv​.fr/​f​r​/​c​h​a​r​t​e​-​d​e​-​d​e​v​e​l​o​p​p​e​m​e​n​t​-​r​e​s​p​o​n​s​a​b​l​e​-​d​e​s​-​n​e​u​r​o​t​e​c​h​n​o​l​o​g​i​e​s​-​87964
5https://​www​.human​brain​pro​ject​.eu/en/
6https://​brain​ini​tia​tive​.nih​.gov/

Our world through the lens of science. Every week, in your inbox.

Get the newsletter